Jury Nullification
and the Rule of Law
Men do not make
laws. They do but discover them. Laws must be justified by something
more than the will of the majority. They must rest on the eternal
foundation of righteousness. That state is most fortunate in its form of
government which has the aptest instruments for the discovery of law.
Calvin Coolidge, to the Massachusetts State Senate,
January 7, 1914
Do justice, sir, do justice.
Learned Hand
Not long after the end of the original O.J. Simpson trial, I got in a
little argument in the mail room with one of my colleagues at Los Angeles
Valley College, Farrell Broslawsky, who teaches history and political
science. He said that the O.J. verdict was an example of "jury
nullification" and that the whole idea of jury nullification was a
violation of the rule of law. Since then, I have seen the same argument
made elsewhere, and I think it is important to address it.
"Jury nullification" means that a jury finds a defendant
innocent because the law itself is unjust, or is unjust in a particular
application, and so should not be applied. Since no O.J. jurors expressed
or implied opposition to the laws against murder, their verdict was
certainly not an example of nullification in that sense. Nor did any
jurors admit that they were persuaded of O.J.'s guilt but that they
thought it was OK for him to have committed the murders anyway. Instead,
jurors simply said that they accepted the defense argument that police
carelessness and possible misconduct, motivated by racism, introduced an
element of reasonable doubt against the prosecution's case. Since Judge
Ito allowed the defense to make that argument (judges typically do not
allow defense lawyers to make pleas for nullification), it certainly
doesn't look like a nullification case. The jury may have been more
suspicious of the police than was reasonable, but that was the luck of the
draw in the jury pool--a jury in Santa Monica later found O.J. liable for
the murder, under the less rigorous standard of "preponderance of the
evidence," rather than "beyond a reasonable doubt," in the
civil case against him.
On the other hand, does a jury have the power and the right to
nullify the law? Would nullification be a violation of the principle of
the rule of law? Yes, and no, respectively. It is common today for judges
to tell prospective jurors that they must apply the law as he gives it to
them and that their business is simply to determine whether the defendant
has broken the law or not. But that is not what was intended by the right
to trial by jury in the Bill or Rights. Thomas Jefferson said in 1782 (Notes
on Virginia):
...it is usual for the jurors to decide the fact, and to refer the law
arising on it to the decision of the judges. But this division of the
subject lies with their discretion only. And if the question relate to
any point of public liberty, or if it be one of those in which the
judges may be suspected of bias, the jury undertake to decide both law
and fact.
Then, recommending trial by jury to the French in 1789, Jefferson wrote
to Tom Paine, "I consider...[trial by jury] as the only anchor ever
yet imagined by man, by which a government can be held to the principles
of its constitution...."
One may say that Jefferson is not talking about nullification, but just
about a jury taking the interpretation of the law into its own
hands--though that is already well beyond what a jury is allowed to do
now, especially if a jury undertook to apply its own interpretation of the
Bill of Rights. On the other hand, we have the District of Columbia
Circuit Court of Appeals, in Unites States v. Dougherty, 1972,
saying:
[The jury has an] unreviewable and irreversible power...to acquit in
disregard of the instructions on the law given by the trial judge...The
pages of history shine on instances of the jury's exercise of its
prerogative to disregard uncontradicted evidence and instructions of the
judge; for example, acquittals under the fugitive slave law.
Indeed, if juries do not have the right and power to nullify the law,
we must face the fact that Harriet Tubman, one of the great
heroines of American history, would and should have been guilty of
multiple federal crimes by violating the fugitive slave laws. That
is a morally revolting prospect, but judges today who reject nullification
must confess that they would enforce the fugitive slave laws and convict
Harriet Tubman. If they were to honestly admit as much, and hold
themselves powerless to disobey unjust and morally despicable laws, they
should be told that "obeying orders" was not accepted as a
defense in the Nazi war crime trials at Nuremberg.
It is tempting to say that today we don't have laws like the
"fugitive slave laws." That would be a serious self-deception.
The prisons are full of people who have done nothing wrong, except be in
possession of a "controlled substance" that the federal
government, at least, has no authority under the Constitution to
"control." People dying of cancer or AIDS have
been arrested and jailed just for growing and smoking marijuana, the only
thing that enables them to eat, take their medication, and stay alive.
Despite the passage of medical marijuana laws in many states, as far apart
as California and Maine, federal prosecutors have viciously targeted
medical mairjuana activists, who are often very ill themselves, and have
found pliant judges who prohibit medical necessity defenses.
But must we simply accept such possible injustices in order to uphold
the rule of law? By allowing jury nullification, do we not license the
misuse of the principle, as when Southern white juries would acquit
KKK'ers for murdering or terrorizing blacks or Jews? Unfortunately, as
long as we have trials, by jury or otherwise, it will be possible for bias
to misuse the law and perpetrate injustices. KKK'ers would have gotten
acquitted because a large part of (white) public opinion, and the staff of
the courts themselves, was biased in their favor. Regardless of the duties
of judges or juries, a means was going to be found in such circumstances
to prevent their conviction. The remedy for that is a system of checks and
balances. A local jurisdiction, whether in police or courts, that allows
KKK'ers to murder people and get away with it is violating the 14th
Amendment by denying the "equal protection of the law," making
itself liable to federal civil rights intervention, as was vigorously
pursued by Ulysses S.
Grant, before the shameful capitulation of the Republicans, after
Grant was gone, in 1876.
Does jury nullification contribute to, rather than mitigate, such
judicial misbehavior? No, because it is part of the system of checks and
balances itself -- a check against the bias of judges and the
irrationality and corruption that creeps steadily into the law, as
irresponsible legislators and judges think about things other than
justice. Jury nullification is not a violation of the rule of law because it
is part of the rule of law. It represents a basic misconception of the
principle of the "rule of law" itself to say that it means that
everyone absolutely must obey the law until the law can be changed by the
appropriate processes. Indeed, that conception of the rule of law
would forbid civil disobedience, which was justified by Martin Luther
King, quoting St. Augustine, that, "An unjust law is no law at
all." But how can we have the rule of law if we accept something like
that? How can people just go around judging for themselves whether a law
is just or not? The answer is, that they have to, and that is simply the
principle of moral conscience. The rule of law is not contrary to
that; for the rule of law is not an injunction to blind
obedience. Instead, the rule of law is a principle of the limitation
of the authority of government.
To be "ruled by laws, not by men," is the old expression.
Now, a jury nullifying a law or a protester practicing civil disobedience
is not engaged in ruling. Instead, they are doing the precise opposite:
negating the instructions and actions of government. The principle of the
rule of law does the same kind of thing, for it means that the authority
and power of government and of individuals in office is limited to those
spheres, those issues, and those actions that are specified by the law.
The rule of law denies to government unlimited or discretionary power and
authority. The rule of law is thus part of a system of checks and balances
to prevent dictatorship and despotism. Because of that, it is curiously
the case that you do not need to have laws to have the rule of law: for
the whole system of Common Law developed through the practice of the
courts in considering claims that someone had committed a wrong. The
original purpose of trial by jury in the Magna Carta was similar. The
threat, indeed, addressed by the Magna Carta was of the laws and judges of
King John. If
Magna Carta juries could not nullify the laws of King John, or ignore the
instructions and rulings of his judges, trial by jury would have been a
useless protection. But the Barons, in obtaining King John's pledge, as
Lysander Spooner wrote in 1852, "were engaged in no such senseless
work as that."
The jury is the last line of defense, the last check and balance,
against tyrannical government, if, that is, it is charged with determining
the justice of a case and not just with blindly applying the law as given
by a judge. It was become a very interesting perversion of the sytem of
checks and balances when, as we are told, the Constitution means whatever
the Supreme Court says it means but that we are then expected to obey
without resistance. Since the Supreme Court has in general, since the New
Deal, interpreted the Constitution to mean exactly the opposite of
its original purpose, which had been to establish a federal government of limited
and enumerated powers, but which now seems to have gotten us a
national government of unlimited and plenary powers, which
can legislate or regulate in any matter whatsoever, what we have seen is
the destruction of the rule of law, through the arbitrary
authority of an irresponsible court, rather than its preservation.
When the citizen demands that the government obey the Constitution, and
the government replies that it is obeying its interpretation of the
Constitution, which gives it authority and discretion far beyond that
overthrown in the American Revolution, then the whole idea of the
"rule of law" has been turned around to justify the very kind of
arbitrary, discretionary, and unaccountable authority that it was supposed
to prevent.
The interpretation of the law cannot be trusted to those with the power
to enforce it also. The separation of powers between the judiciary and the
executive in the federal government was not sufficient to prevent this, as
Thomas Jefferson already
understood: "How can we expect impartial decision between the
General government, of which they are themselves so eminent a part, and an
individual State, from which they have nothing to hope or fear?" The
federal courts are part of the federal government and will tend to take
its side in the long run. This is precisely what has happened.
Hence we return to Jefferson's maxim that only trial by jury can hold a
government to the "principles of its consitution." Since, as a
matter of fact, a jury can practice nullification even if the judge tells
it that it can't, because its deliberations are secret and unrecorded,
trial by jury is still, as long as jurors are brave and informed, one of
the most important protections for freedom. Most Americans on jury duty
blindly obey the judge, but occasionally feelings run high enough in
important cases for juries to ignore the judge and do the right thing.
In defending the rule of law but also complaining about judicial
activism, Thomas Sowell says:
A judge cannot "do justice" directly in the case before him.
This view was strongly expressed in a small episode in the life of
Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes. After having lunch with Judge Learned
Hand, Holmes entered his carriage to be driven away. As he left, Judge
Hand's parting salute was:
"Do justice, sir, do justice."
Holmes ordered the carriage stopped.
"That is not my job," Holmes said to Judge Hand. "It
is my job to apply the law."
[The Quest for Cosmic Justice, The Free Press, 1999, p. 169]
Although Sowell is properly concerned about the erosion of the rule of
law by judicial activism in the service of "cosmic" and
totalitarian ideology, he and Justice Holmes are wrong in this. The law is
supposed to be an instrument of justice, and judges, like any morally
conscientious persons, have a duty to see that justice is done. What is
required, of course, is a proper sense of justice, which is to respect
things like property rights that have been trashed by 20th century
American courts. As it happens, property rights are protected by the
Constitution, the supreme law of the land. Any judge who threw out an
indictment that violated the "Takings" clause of the Fifth
Amendment is thus very properly repecting the law -- respecting it as it
has not been respected by even the Supreme Court since the New Deal. It is
only a belief in blind obedience (to the dishonest Supreme Court), not the
rule of law, that prevents judges from doing this.
Recently, a federal
judge in Los Angeles prohibited a cancer patient from smoking marijuana
while on bail, even though he would become more ill, and might even die,
without it, just because such an exemption would violate the very laws
that the patient was being accused of violating. The judge, however
"sympathetic" to the "plight" of the dying man, could
not authorize a violation of the law. However, in a related medical
marijuana case, the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals subsequently sent back
a judgment for reconsideration because the trial judge had not allowed
"medical necessity" as a consideration in his opinion.
"Necessity," indeed, is an old common law defense: If
someone must violate a law or die, one has a perfectly valid reason for
violating the law. No "judicial activist" made this up, but the
trial judges in both the cases mentioned would not allow it. Who is
respecting the rule of law in these cases? The judge who sadly knows that
he may be condemning a man to death, or a judge who appeals to an ancient
and reasonable exception to laws that are inappropriately applied? In the
former, the judge is both a bad judge, rejecting the existing tools
of justice, and a bad man, for not at least recusing himself
lest he be forced by a perverse duty to do evil. One hopes that something
like applying the Nuremberg Laws or the fugitive slave laws would have
been too much for Justice Holmes.
I should note in closing, however, that government conducts much of its
business today through administrative
rulings and penalties that are imposed summarily, without trial by
jury, or often without trial at all. This is becoming the most convenient instrument
of tyranny open to modern American government. At the same time,
judges who are hostile to nullification, and who have the power of
arbitrarily imposing "contempt of court" penalties without trial
by jury, or even legal explanation, are beginning to use their powers to
intrude on the deliberation processes of juries, trying to make jurors
answerable for deliberations that traditionally and constitutionally have
been secret, unrecorded, and unreviewable. But, as Jefferson would have
said, it is not surprising to see such devices used, by those with tyranny
in their hearts, to expand their own power and the domination of
government.
Fully
Informed Jury Association
Quotes on the Powers and Duties of
Juries
An Oath for Jurors